William McNeill
In his lecture course of winter semester 1925-26, Logic: The Question of Truth, Heidegger makes a claim that will be altogether programmatic for Being and Time and for his phenomenological work of the 1920s. “The concept of possibility,” he remarks, “is entirely unclarified in scientific philosophy hitherto. [...] The meaning of possibility and the type of structures of possibility belonging to Dasein as such have remained altogether concealed from us up to the present day” (GA 21 228).1 The radicality of this claim can scarcely be underestimated: Heidegger, in his work of the 1920s and beyond, will in effect inaugurate a new thinking of possibility that will exceed the parameters set by the first, Greek beginning of philosophy, which became established in Aristotle’s ontology. Central to this re-examination of possibility is, as this quotation intimates, the uncovering of Dasein as the site where possibility itself is opened up in a most radical way. In my present remarks I shall begin to trace what I regard as Heidegger’s radical displacement and rethinking of both the concept and the phenomenon of possibility in his magnum opus of 1927, Being and Time. The Introduction to that work indeed provides a first indication of this displacement in its assertion that “[h]igher than actuality stands possibility. The understanding of phenomenology lies solely in taking it up as a possibility” (SZ 38). This statement not only announces what appears to be a reversal of the traditional priority of actuality over possibility—a priority that goes back to Aristotle’s privileging of energeia over dunamis—but also sees phenomenology itself as one possibility of philosophizing, a possibility that, when taken up and enacted in its own radicalization, may itself undergo transformation, as did Heidegger’s own phenomenological thinking of the 1920s. The transformation and eventual abandonment of phenomenology from 1930 on as inadequate or inappropriate to the thinking of Being is not unrelated, I would suggest, to the rethinking of possibility that Being and Time initiates.
In the present essay I shall suggest that inherent to Heidegger’s rethinking of possibility are two, seemingly irreconcilable claims: first, that—contrary to what much of the political rhetoric of our time would have us believe—not everything is possible. And second, that, nevertheless, Dasein, by its very way of existing, makes possible even the impossible. What these claims entail, I shall try to elucidate with respect to Heidegger’s thinking of possibility in Being and Time. To this end, I want to begin to trace the contours of this rethinking of possibility via the analytic of Dasein presented in Being and Time by outlining six key points of the analysis. These points, taken together, emphatically indicate the centrality and primacy of the phenomenon of possibility for the entire phenomenology of Dasein.
The ontological determination of Dasein—that is, of the being that we ourselves in each case are—is primarily possibility. “Dasein,” Heidegger writes, “is not something present at hand that in addition has [or possesses] the ability to do something; rather, it is primarily being-possible [Möglichsein]. Dasein is in each case what it can be and how it is its possibility” (SZ 143). We are not primarily something actual that has the additional feature of being able to do something, or of having possibilities. Rather, insofar as we are actual, this being actual, this actuality of ourselves as actual, is already held or suspended, as it were, within the dimension of possibility. Moreover, we do not simply have possibilities, we are possibility: our being is primarily being-possible. Possibility in this sense, Heidegger emphasizes, is not to be understood as that which is not yet actual; it is not a modal category that is ontologically lesser than actuality or necessity:
The being-possible that Dasein in each case is existentially [i.e., ontologically, in terms of its very being] is to be distinguished just as much from empty, logical possibility as from the contingency that attends something present at hand insofar as something can “happen” to the latter. As a modal category of presence at hand, possibility signifies that which is not yet actual and that which is not always necessary. It characterizes the merely possible. Possibility as an existential, by contrast, is the most primordial [or originary] and ultimate positive ontological determinacy of Dasein; initially, [...] it can only be prepared as a problem. (143-44)
The centrality and primacy of possibility for Dasein’s being could scarcely be more emphatically stated. Several points bear emphasizing with regard to this initial sketch. First, if possibility, in the sense of being-possible, is not to be understood as that which is not yet actual, it is because it is that which already is, the dimension within which everything actual is already suspended. But this indicates only that the being of possibility, its already being, is not reducible to, and cannot be understood phenomenologically in terms of, actuality. What kind of being pertains, then, to possibility? What is strange, peculiar, even uncanny “actuality,” or perhaps better, force? In what way is Dasein as possibility? Second, in hinting that the modern, Kantian understanding of possibility as a modal category refers to the not yet actual and the not always necessary, Heidegger indicates how the traditional understanding of being as primarily the actuality of presence at hand has itself led to a reductive understanding of the possible as that which is less than either the plenitude of actual presence or of that which always is, the eternal. The task of the phenomenology of Dasein, unfolding in and through a destructuring of the history of ontology, will thus be to begin to think—or to prepare, if only as a problem—the being of possibility outside or beyond the parameters of the traditional prioritizing of presence or actuality. Third—and this is a more general point—we might do well to remind ourselves here that to exist primarily as being-possible characterizes not only the being of Dasein, but the being of the living in general. If all living is a being underway, then every living being, as living, has always already surpassed what and how it actually is, surpassed it in entering into and maintaining itself within the dimension of possibility or potentiality: its living is its being capable, its possibility of being otherwise than it already is. Where such a being is no longer able to breathe, to sense, to nourish itself, or to die: there we say the being is dead. And correlatively, death is a possibility only for the living. Of course, there is much more to be said here, and we cannot simply conclude from this that being means the same thing for Dasein as it does for other living beings, or that being-possible is the same, or that death and death are the same. For it is not possibility as such, Heidegger will argue, that is the sole or critical issue here, but the relation to possibility, the opening up of possibility as possibility.2
This question of the opening up of possibility as such, as possibility—an opening up that Heidegger will elsewhere describe as an “irruption” into possibility—brings us to a second major point (GA 29/30 531; Metaphysics 365). Not just Dasein itself as possibility, but the being of all beings, is first opened up, as possibility, in what Heidegger terms “projection” (Entwerfen). Projection is what enables understanding, which is always an understanding of the being of beings. Dasein understands not only itself in terms of what and how it can be, in terms of its potential for being (Seinkönnen), but also and at the same time all other beings within the world: we understand the tree, the wood, the table in terms of what and how they can be, what we can do with them, how we can let them be, and so on. The tree grows, flourishes, or decays, but the possibilities of its growth, flourishing, or decay are not disclosed as possibilities except in and through the projective happening of Dasein. Likewise, we understand the other Dasein in terms of how we can be with him or her in terms of our worldly engagements. At one and the same time as this opening up of other beings as such, as potentially being this or that, what is opened up is the horizon of a world, in terms of which or from out of which beings are given as a whole.3 Already in Being and Time, Heidegger describes this projective opening up of possibility in terms of an antecedent giving, a freeing and releasing (Freigabe) that first enables beings to appear within a world: “the freeing of intraworldly beings releases these beings with respect to their possibilities” (SZ 144). Projection thus opens up the realm of freedom: it opens up both the being of Dasein and the being of other beings in terms of the meaningful possibilities that are given within a particular world—a world that, as we shall later indicate, is also always already given as a historical world. As projection, understanding “projects the being of Dasein with respect to that for the sake of which it exists with equal primordiality as it projects Dasein’s being with respect to the significance that constitutes the worldliness of a particular world” (145). That for the sake of which Dasein exists is its own potential for being, the possibility of its own being, or its own being as possibility. Yet such being, as being-in-the-world, is never separable from, but is intimately bound up with, the being of other beings that have appeared within a world, and, before and beyond this, with the world itself that constitutes the primary horizon in terms of which such beings appear. This antecedent binding or directedness constitutes Dasein’s facticity;4 projection opens up what Heidegger terms the “leeway of [Dasein’s] factical potential for being” (145).
A third point follows from this. The “fact” of facticity—which, like possibility itself, can at this stage be grasped only as a “problem” (SZ 56)—constitutes, as it were, an ineluctable restriction on the freedom of Dasein as possibility. To say that Dasein is primarily possibility does not mean that it is sheer, free-floating possibility, an undifferentiated freedom that can be determined by the will: “[p]ossibility as an existential does not mean a free-floating potential for being in the sense of the ‘liberty of indifference’ (libertas indifferentiae)” (SZ 144). Dasein’s freedom is not absolute: to say that it exists for the sake of its own being is not the equivalent of autonomy, for its own being is a being-in-the-world, and thus a being that never entirely belongs to Dasein as a self. This is to say that all projection is “thrown” (geworfen), and this thrownness complicates and restrains the freedom opened up in projection. Dasein is “thrown possibility through and through” (144). This thrownness also comprises the way in which Dasein has already “found” itself, its bodily attunement in its here-and-now situation in the world:
Finding itself essentially attuned and situated [...] Dasein has in each case already entered into particular possibilities. As that potential for being that it is, it has let certain possibilities pass it by; it is constantly waiving possibilities of its being, taking them up or mistaking them. This means, however, that Dasein is being-possible that has been delivered over to itself, thrown possibility through and through. (144)
The possibility of being has in each case its own history—who and how I can be at the next moment depends on and comes out of, approaches me from, who and how I have been, not exclusively (for it also depends on events and beings beyond my history), but nevertheless essentially—and yet this history can never entirely own itself, for it is enabled by and already inscribed within (thrown into) a greater history, which is that of a historical world. As directed in advance toward a world that precedes and exceeds it, Dasein’s being as possibility is always situated by, and only ever responsive to, an already prevailing historical world into which it has been thrown. Not everything is possible in any given era or at any given time.
I shall come back to this point. For now, I want to highlight what Dasein’s having already found itself as possibility necessarily implies, namely, that such possibility has also and unavoidably already lost itself, that it can never entirely be itself. Which is to say that the possibility that I can be, can, nevertheless, never be mine, can never appropriate itself. I can only ever pursue this possibility of being. I can only ever anticipate this possibility of being that I potentially can and must be, yet never will be. (This anticipation, this pursuit, is what Heidegger will designate as a “running ahead” [Vorlaufen]—which, as pursuit, is always a running after, a running after something that has shown itself—the running ahead that constitutes Dasein’s very way of being, or Dasein itself as way, as the opening up of a path, a path that is not pregiven, but opened up only in a being underway.) Heidegger insists that this loss is not only possible, but necessary and inevitable: it is intrinsic to the being of possibility, to the possibility of being. Through projection, Dasein understands itself, the potential for being that it is:
And only because Dasein is its There in the manner of understanding [i.e., projection] can it run astray [sich verlaufen, this time] and be mistaken with regard to itself. And insofar as understanding finds itself attuned and situated, and as such exposed existentially to thrownness, Dasein has in each case already run astray and failed to recognize itself. In its potential for being it is, therefore, delivered over to [überantwortet: more literally, it must answer or respond to] the possibility of first finding itself again in its possibilities. (SZ 144)
Dasein, as the potential for being, has always yet to appropriate itself in terms of what is possible for it at any moment. Yet the necessity of this task is only a testament to the antecedent disappropriation to which it itself, as the potential for being, is exposed. Disappropriation, the force of thrownness, which is that of a continual being thrown, or finding oneself “in the throw,” is primary here; appropriation is secondary and can occur only after the event (the event of being that Heidegger will later term Ereignis). We have always yet to be, we have always yet to find ourselves again in terms of the possibilities of our being, only because we have always already lost ourselves. As Heidegger elsewhere puts it: “Possibility falls away, and an ever new appropriation is called for” (GA 18 190).
Now this possibility, namely, “the possibility of first finding itself again in its possibilities”—this possibility is not just any possibility (SZ 144). As the primary possibility that Dasein is, it is an altogether distinctive one, even though—and this is what is most peculiar—it is not a determinate one, despite what the grammatical use of the definite article might seem to indicate here. This leads us to our fourth point.
Dasein as possibility is, in Being and Time, thought hyperbolically, as it were, in terms of its most extreme possibility: that of its death, of the possibility of impossibility. This negativity, the “not” of impossibility, continually haunts Dasein as the being that exists as possibility. Where there is possibility—where possibility is disclosed as such, as possibility—there lies, necessarily, the possibility of impossibility, of failure, of not actualizing or realizing, of not accomplishing, what could have been and nevertheless was not to be. Is this not to say that Dasein makes possible even the impossible—not in the sense of actualizing it, but in the sense of letting the impossible be as a possibility, of raising even the impossible into the dimension or element of the possible? Indeed.5 Yet, one might argue, the converse is surely just as much the case: if the impossible becomes a possibility, everything possible is no less an impossibility. Or to put it another way, every success on Dasein’s part, every actual accomplishment, is, in a sense, an impossibility, for it can never be fully actual. Yet would this not be to reduce possibility to the possibility of actuality, or of pure presence, once again? Far from being an impossibility, all accomplishment (Vollbringen), which Heidegger comes to see as the essence of action, occurs within and actualizes itself (presences) from out of the element of the possible.6 The possible is its very dimension.
Now it is this dimension that Dasein has always already assumed in taking upon itself the possibility of its death as a possibility of being. A number of points need to be emphasized here. First, Dasein has to take upon itself this possibility in order to be: it is not Dasein’s choice; Dasein does not decide to assume or take on this possibility. Thus, Heidegger writes: “whenever Dasein exists, it is also already thrown into this possibility” (SZ 251). It is thrown into this possibility as into the mode of being of projecting itself, for being thrown into this possibility first enables and anchors projection as such.7 To be thrown into this possibility means: to have been projected, continually and already, in the direction of and right into this possibility, in a projection that constitutes our very way of being as such. This projection of our way of being as a being toward death as possibility is the primary projection of our being, for, prior to any determinate choice or decision—prior, that is, to any appropriation of this or that possibility on Dasein’s part—it has always already happened. It is as this excess or excedance that will always already have surpassed every determinate possibility that death as possibility is not to be outstripped or surpassed (nicht zu überholen), and it is as this excedance that death as possibility is projected hyperbolically, as “the most extreme” possibility (250). Strictly speaking, Dasein cannot take this possibility upon itself, however, because prior to this hyperbolic projection it is not yet a self, or does not yet have the possibility of being a self. It is the subjection (of something that is not yet Dasein) to this projection that first enables and necessitates individuation, that makes this most extreme possibility Dasein’s “ownmost” possibility. It first brings Dasein before itself: “[w]ith death, Dasein stands before itself in its ownmost potential for being” (250). To say that this possibility is Dasein’s ownmost possibility, however, does not mean that Dasein owns this possibility. Quite the contrary: for to say that Dasein owns this possibility would mean that Dasein had exceeded or outstripped it. Rather, being thrown into this possibility means having been subjected to, having undergone, the disappropriation that first enables any and all appropriation. This possibility has taken hold of, has—quite literally—possessed, Dasein. We seen here the entire paradox of Dasein’s “mineness” or (in a weak, non-modern sense) “subjectivity”: what is most my own, that which no one else can undergo for me or in my place, is nevertheless not my own—it is not something I own or possess, or dispose over.
Second, however, death as possibility, as “the possibility of the impossibility” of existence as such, is not the possibility of nonbeing, or of sheer nothingness, but a possibility of being (SZ 262). Or rather, if it is the possibility of nonbeing, or of impossibility—of the impossibility of “my” existence—then the genitive here does not signify a relation of belonging. This possibility does not belong to nonbeing or to impossibility. It belongs to being as such as its innermost preserve. Dasein relates to this possibility of impossibility constantly and always in one way or another; its relation to this possibility is what constitutes Dasein as mortal and its way of being as dying. Dying, in this existential-ontological conception, is not, therefore, a one-off event that occurs at or near the end of a life; rather, “[d]ying is to be taken as a title designating that way of being in which Dasein is in relation to its death” (247). Dasein, accordingly, “is factically dying, so long as it exists” (SZ 259).8
Third, and very briefly, I want to draw attention here to the profoundly paradoxical and aporetic structure of this happening of death, of this being toward death as the possibility of impossibility. It is paradoxical not only because the impossible is not the opposite of the possible here, and is thus precisely possible as im-possible; it is also paradoxical because death as this possibility is on the one hand utterly determinate—it is irremediably mine and as such absolutely certain—and yet indeterminate, as that which “is possible at any moment” (SZ 258). This paradoxical structure indeed constitutes, Heidegger says, “the ownmost character of possibility pertaining to death: certain and yet indeterminate, that is, possible at any moment” (258). This determinate indeterminacy is fundamentally temporal: it is the indeterminacy of the future that, as indeterminacy, precisely already is—which, however, is to say that it is within the determinacy of the unfolding of my thrownness, my having-been. It is the element within and from out of which my being thrown unfolds.
Dasein’s relation to possibility is, precisely through this hyperbolic projection, shown to be one of anticipation or “running ahead” (Vorlaufen)—but this means that its relation to possibility is always futural in the radical, ekstatic sense that Heidegger gives this futuricity. In its average everydayness, Dasein tends to avoid, to conceal and cover over, the most extreme and ownmost possibility of its own being by falling, by interpreting itself in terms of determinate possibilities, ways of being proffered by others and by a world into which it has been thrown. Seeking to actualize itself through action in enacting “real life,” it forgets itself in its ownmost possibility, loses itself in the “They.” It overlooks or fails to see the very element of the possible. In contrast to such evasive being toward death as possibility, Heidegger, in section 53, sketches what an authentic being toward death must entail. Dasein’s maintaining itself (sich halten9) in an authentic being toward death, as a way of being in relation to this possibility, must, by contrast, not evade or cover over this possibility, but let it be as a possibility. An authentic being toward this possibility, as a way of being, cannot mean actualizing this possibility: within the field of everyday concern, which is concerned to actualize possibilities, such actualization “has the tendency to annihilate [or abolish] the possibility of the possible” by actualizing it (even though, Heidegger notes, such actualization is only ever relative); in terms of the possibility of my death, actualizing this possibility, perhaps through suicide, would abolish the possibility of being in relation to this very possibility (SZ 261). In an authentic being toward death this possibility must, by contrast, “be understood without being weakened [or, hyperbolically: ungeschwächt] as possibility, be cultivated as possibility, and in relating to it, be sustained as possibility” (261).10 Such being toward possibility is termed a “running ahead into possibility [Vorlaufen in die Möglichkeit]” (261). Now such running ahead, which is a projection and thus a disclosive understanding of possibility, not only unveils possibility as such, as Heidegger writes, but it unveils it hyperbolically, as that which has “altogether no measure,” as “the possibility of the measureless impossibility of existence” (262). In a sense, it intensifies or enhances possibility, but only because this possibility is already there, latent within all existing as such. It brings to the fore the measureless within the very possibility of existence (and the measureless here also means: that which cannot be measured, thus calculated, the incalculable). To say, therefore, that “[b]eing toward death, as a running ahead into possibility, first possibilizes11 [ermöglicht] this possibility and sets it free [or releases it] as such” does not, it would seem, mean that running ahead first makes possible this possibility, but only that it intensifies this possibility that is already there—and yet not yet there as possibility, not yet unveiled and set free as such (262; my emphasis in bold). It is running ahead into the possibility of impossibility—into the impossibility of existence as such, which is to say, into the impossibility of possibility, the impossibility that attends all possibility—it is this running ahead that first releases the possibility of existence as such, first lets it be as the possibility it is. Yet if running ahead unveils, hyperbolically, the possibility of the impossibility of existence, this is only because this authentic mode of being is itself only the retrieval, the self-recovery or auto-recovery, as it were, of that very way of being that first enables itself as possibility: “[b]eing toward death is running ahead into a potential for being of that being whose mode of being is running ahead itself” (262). Running ahead, thus retrieved (wiederholt), therefore means: understanding oneself in the very movedness of one’s being, existing fully within the unfolding of one’s ownmost being from out of its ultimate ground.
The phenomenon of running ahead articulates the movement of Dasein’s being, its way of being as being always already ahead of itself, which is the primary moment of Care. Dasein’s being ahead of itself is its projective being toward itself as potentiality for being, as possibility:
Being toward its ownmost potentiality for being means ontologically, however: Dasein is in each case already ahead of itself in its being. Dasein is always already ‘out beyond itself,’not as a relating to other beings that it is not, but as being toward the potential for being that it itself is. (SZ 191-92)
Now this being ahead of itself first enables Dasein’s coming toward itself as a coming back to itself, a return to or retrieval of itself as a thrown having been, as being-there-in-the-world. Yet this not only means, once again, that the Dasein whose being is enabled as possibility, in and through this being ahead of itself—that such Dasein is not yet—never yet—itself. It also means, more radically, that this primary “not yet” that Dasein is does not belong to Dasein itself, to Dasein as an already existing self, for it first enables Dasein’s coming toward itself, that is, it first enables the appropriation of itself that has always yet to happen. It is this, Dasein’s coming toward itself, that constitutes the ekstatic phenomenon of the future, according to Being and Time. In section 65, Heidegger unfolds this sense of future phenomenologically starting from the phenomenon of being toward death. Dasein’s being toward its ownmost possibility
is possible only in such a way that Dasein can come toward itself in its ownmost possibility in general, and sustains this possibility as possibility in this letting itself come toward itself. Such letting itself come toward itself in this distinctive possibility and sustaining this possibility is the original phenomenon of the future” (325).
“Future” here, Heidegger emphasizes in alluding to the sense of coming or approach (Kunft) inherent in the German Zukunft, does not mean a “now” or present that is not yet actual and has yet to be, but means that coming in which Dasein comes toward itself in its ownmost potential for being. Just as possibility is the primary and most originary determination of Dasein’s being, so the ekstatic phenomenon of the future is primary within the unity of the ekstases, first enabling having-been and the yet more derivative presence that futural having-been “awakens” (329). It is the disappropriation that grounds the possibility of the future—of the future as the possibility of Dasein’s coming toward itself—it is this disappropriation, however, which is thus also more primordial than having been, that undermines the coherence and unity of the supposedly self-like, unitary structure of ekstatic temporality as “the ekstatikon pure and simple,” as “the originary ‘outside itself’ in and for itself,” thereby grounding the very selfhood of Dasein in irrecoverable loss (329).
Indeed, this “not yet,” the ekstatic happening of this originary future or coming as the grounding possibility of Dasein, is so primordial that one must question whether the term “disappropriation” adequately articulates what is to be thought here. For “disappropriation” implies that appropriation has already occurred, that Dasein has already been constituted as such to thus undergo the expropriation of its being. Yet must there not be a closure that antecedes, or is more primordial than, such disappropriation, if the future is indeed more primordial than having been, if having been (Gewesenheit) “in a certain way first springs from the future” (SZ 326)? This, presumably, is why Heidegger here, in discussing the finitude of the future, writes not of a disappropriation, disowning, or expropriation, but of a closure as the most fundamental characteristic of the futural ekstasis—a closure that first opens the possibility of projecting or understanding one’s own being in terms of nothingness (Nichtigkeit) or the possibility of impossibility: a closure, therefore, that first opens possibility as such. The fundamental question concerns
how such coming-toward-oneself is itself originarily determined as such. Its finitude does not primarily mean a cessation, but is a characteristic of temporalization itself. The originary and authentic future is the toward-oneself, oneself, [already] existing as the unsurpassable possibility of nothingness. The ekstatic character of the originary future lies precisely in the fact that it closes our potential for being, that is, it is itself closed, and as such makes possible [ermöglicht] a radically open existentiell understanding of nothingness. (330)
Heidegger here indicates how this primordial, originating closure, this closed (geschlossen) dimension of the future, first enables an authentically and radically open (entschlossen) projection of one’s own being upon the possibility of the impossibility of existence, or the possibility of nothingness.12 Authenticity, an authentic relation to one’s ownmost finitude, is thus itself a derivative possibility of being in the sense that it is grounded in and presupposes this more primordial closure. Even though the originary and authentic future share the same formal structure of the “toward-oneself,” Heidegger here suggests that they do not coincide: it is the originary future that first enables or makes possible the authentic future as an explicit running ahead, a recuperation or retrieval of a movement of being that has always already happened.
This futural dimension of Dasein’s Being must ultimately be understood in terms of historicality: that is, in relation to the phenomenon of “birth” that testifies to what Heidegger calls “the quiet force of the possible [die stille Kraft des Möglichen]” (SZ 394-95). What is important here is that it is the irrecoverable loss of presence, the finitude implicit in Dasein’s futural ekstasis, which is essentially closed, compelling the disappropriation in being toward death, that first gives birth to individuation, and thereby to finite possibilities of being. The disclosive running ahead into possibility as such, sustaining the possibility of impossibility, individuates Dasein in casting it back upon and returning it to its factical There, turning it toward and into the horizon of possibilities that approach it from out of an already existing world. Dasein’s birth, its coming into being as the birth of the possible, which is the originary event of individuation, is implicit within, and compelled by, the closure of the future that constitutes Dasein as being toward death. Just as death, ontologically conceived, is not an event at the end of life, so too birth is not an event at the beginning. “Factical Dasein,” Heidegger emphasizes, “exists in the manner of birth, and in being born it is also already dying in the sense of being toward death” (374).13
The factical historicality of Dasein, as the concrete, horizonal event that coincides with the birth of the possible, is thematized in Being and Time in response to the question of the source of the factical possibilities of existence (SZ 383). The factically disclosed possibilities of existence cannot, as such, be drawn from death as possibility, since the latter precisely has no content and no measure. Rather, Dasein’s way of being ahead of itself, as being toward death, intrinsically casts or directs it back toward the factical, already existing world that is in itself a world of others, a world borne and sustained by the already existent Dasein of others to which it has been abandoned, a world that thus precedes—and, as an event, continues to precede—each and every birth. Each and every birth of Dasein, as the birth of the possible, is thus nourished in advance, so to speak, by the historical ground or “heritage” (Erbe) that it has had to assume in its thrownness (383). And this means that implicit within the very disclosure of the possible there lies concealed a quiet force, a latent power that as yet approaches us, that has yet to arrive, whose content and direction we do not dispose over, but to which we can, at most, be responsive. The openness (Entschlossenheit) of Dasein’s factical coming toward itself as a coming back to its having been “conceals within it a transmission of possibilities that have come down, although not necessarily as having come down” (383).
An explicit openness toward this concealed force of the possible is precisely what is enabled by our anticipatory being toward death, that is, by our running ahead into the dimension of what is possible at any moment, and yet never calculable or determinable: the dimension of indeterminacy that permeates all existence as such. Running ahead into the dimension of possibility to come, Heidegger writes, holds the moment “at the ready”: it brings about (temporalizes) a fundamental readiness for the possibility of a retrieval or recovery of our own having-been, of existence that has been there (SZ 343-44). Yet to the extent that our own having-been is never simply ours, but always also that of a historical world, a heritage, the enactment of this ēthos of openness, this readiness, also bears within it the possibility of an explicit, i.e., knowing, appropriation of one’s heritage—and this is the full sense of “retrieval” (Wiederholung) for Heidegger. Retrieval, writes Heidegger, in the sense of a knowing appropriation of one’s heritage, is neither a reactualizing of a Dasein that has been, nor a return to the past, but is a response or reply—a “reciprocative rejoinder” (Erwiderung)—to a possibility of existence that has been there (386). As such, however, it is a “disavowal” or revocation (Widerruf) of what is working itself out as the past in the present, in the present day.
The task of retrieval, in other words, is understood by Heidegger as essentially critical with regard to the present. It is what he explicitly calls an unmaking or undoing of the present (eine Entgegenwärtigung des Heute14) an undoing that understands history as the “return” of the possible. Such authentic historical inquiry, which is the task of destruction (Destruktion), is a freeing oneself from today, a critique of what appears to be the “present” (SZ 397).15 In other words, destruction as critique retrieves, and in so doing transforms and rethinks, reappropriates, the concealed forces at work in the present day, which for its part is a mere facade of history. It is in this sense that Heidegger invokes “the quiet force of the possible” as that which is to be disclosed by authentic historical inquiry (394): such inquiry has the (always preparatory) task of disclosing history that has been there “in such a way that the ‘force’ of the possible impacts factical existence, that is, approaches that existence in its futural character” (395). The possible, this force of the possible, is that which approaches us from out of what has been: it is what will be appropriated in and through a thinking that remains always yet to come.
***
By way of conclusion, I would simply like to indicate that the significance of Heidegger’s rethinking of possibility in Being and Time is signaled by his own retrieval of precisely this theme and by his renewed appeal to “the quiet force of the possible” at the beginning of what is arguably his most important text from the 1940s, the “Letter on ‘Humanism.’” In this later essay, Heidegger writes, holds the moment “at the ready”: it brings about (temporalizes) a fundamental readiness for the possibility of a retrieval or recovery of our own having-been, of existence that has been there (SZ 343-44). Yet to the extent that our own having-been is never simply ours, but always also that of a historical world, a heritage, the enactment of this ēthos of openness, this readiness, also bears within it the possibility of an explicit, i.e., knowing, appropriation of one’s heritage—and this is the full sense of “retrieval” (Wiederholung) for Heidegger. Retrieval, writes Heidegger, in the sense of a knowing appropriation of one’s heritage, is neither a reactualizing of a Dasein that has been, nor a return to the past, but is a response or reply—a “reciprocative rejoinder” (Erwiderung)—to a possibility of existence that has been there (386). As such, however, it is a “disavowal” or revocation (Widerruf) of what is working itself out as the past in the present, in the present day.
The task of retrieval, in other words, is understood by Heidegger as essentially critical with regard to the present. It is what he explicitly calls an unmaking or undoing of the present (eine Entgegenwärtigung des Heute14) an undoing that understands history as the “return” of the possible. Such authentic historical inquiry, which is the task of destruction (Destruktion), is a freeing oneself from today, a critique of what appears to be the “present” (SZ 397).15 In other words, destruction as critique retrieves, and in so doing transforms and rethinks, reappropriates, the concealed forces at work in the present day, which for its part is a mere facade of history. It is in this sense that Heidegger invokes “the quiet force of the possible” as that which is to be disclosed by authentic historical inquiry (394): such inquiry has the (always preparatory) task of disclosing history that has been there “in such a way that the ‘force’ of the possible impacts factical existence, that is, approaches that existence in its futural character” (395). The possible, this force of the possible, is that which approaches us from out of what has been: it is what will be appropriated in and through a thinking that remains always yet to come.
***
By way of conclusion, I would simply like to indicate that the significance of Heidegger’s rethinking of possibility in Being and Time is signaled by his own retrieval of precisely this theme and by his renewed appeal to “the quiet force of the possible” at the beginning of what is arguably his most important text from the 1940s, the “Letter on ‘Humanism.’” In this later essay, Heidegger again recalls the necessity of freeing our thinking of possibility and of the possible from the orientation of logic and of metaphysics that has dominated the history of philosophy and that thinks possibility and potentiality only in relation to actuality and existentia (that is, in relation to presence, conceived as mere presence-at-hand):
Our words possible [möglich] and possibility [Möglichkeit], under the dominance of “logic” and “metaphysics,” are thought solely in contrast to “actuality”; that is, they are thought on the basis of a definite—the metaphysical—interpretation of being as actus and potentia, a distinction identified with that between existentia and essentia. When I speak of the “quiet force of the possible” I do not mean the possibile of a merely represented possibilitas, nor potentia as the essentia of an actus of existentia; rather, I mean being itself, which in its favoring [mögend] presides over [vermag] thinking and hence over the essence of humanity, and that means over its relation to being. To enable [vermögen] something here means to preserve it in its essence, to maintain it in its element. (GA 9 316-17; “Letter” 242)
The quiet force of the possible is now thought as that of being itself, as the “element” that “enables” (ermöglicht) thinking—a thinking that is more originary than philosophy as determined by the Greek beginning. From the perspective of the “Letter on ‘Humanism’,” we can now appreciate that it is this element, from out of which the historical “destruction” or retrieval of the history of philosophy itself comes to pass, that was first uncovered and exposed as such through the analytic of Dasein in Being and Time. In the “Letter,” the essence of the possible is conceived in terms of an enabling (Vermögen) that refers, not to the capability to accomplish something, as the ability belonging to Dasein or to a “Subject,” but to a more originary “embracing,” “loving,” “bestowal,” or “favoring”—thus in each case to the felicitous giving of a gift, an excess that first gives rise to the possible, that constitutes its very emergence
Thinking is—this says: Being has embraced its [i.e., thinking’s] essence in a destinal manner in each case. To embrace a “thing” or a “person” in their essence means to love them, to favor them. Thought in a more original way, such favoring means the bestowal of their essence as a gift. Such favoring [Mögen] is the proper essence of enabling [Vermögen], which not only can achieve this or that but also can let something essentially unfold in its pro-venance [Her-kunft], that is, let it be. It is on the “strength” [or, by force: “kraft”] of such enabling by favoring that something is properly able to be. This enabling is what is properly “possible” [das “Mögliche”], whose essence resides in favoring. From this favoring being enables thinking. The former makes possible [ermöglicht] the latter. Being is the enabling-favoring, the “may-be” [das “Mög-liche”]. As the element, being is the “quiet force” of the favoring-enabling, that is, of the possible. (GA 9 316; “Letter” 241-42)
Here, the “quiet force” of the possible is thought as the propriative force of being that, in a destinal manner, lets thinking itself be, that is, lets it arrive in its very coming, its provenance. Heidegger here hyphenates the German word for “provenance,” Her-kunft, to indicate once again the primacy of that coming (Kunft), of that originative force that, in Being and Time, was thought in terms of the priority of the futural ekstasis in which Dasein comes toward itself. Here, in the “Letter,” however, this coming is thought in terms of the arrival of being itself as the element of the possible. Heidegger’s discussion of the “quiet force of the possible” in terms of favoring, embrace, and bestowal here, moreover, unfolds what, in Being and Time, remained relatively undeveloped within this invocation of a “quiet” or “gentle” force: namely, that the word Kraft, which in German does not carry the overtones of violence that the English “force” may suggest, is not to be understood in terms of any metaphysical or modern conception of potentiality, power, or energy, but rather in terms of a gentle strength or resourcefulness that comprises the hidden preserve of being.16
In this displacement from the futural happening of Dasein to the destinal happening of being itself as the quiet force of the possible the emphasis is still on the primacy of the “future” as the dimension of the possible. The thinking of being, however, entails a shift into a happening and a force of thrownness from out of this very dimension that antecedes and exceeds any “subjectivity” of Dasein.17 This force of thrownness, the destinal happening of being itself as the transmission and freeing of possibility, neither belongs to Dasein, nor is it a possible “object” of hermeneutic phenomenology, which seeks to appropriate and bring to manifestation, through interpretation, the being of beings that has already been understood implicitly, that is, projected in advance in terms of its possibility. The dominant interpretation and implicit understanding of being in terms of presence-at-hand and actuality, emerging from the Greek beginning of philosophy, is, in Being and Time, traced back “destructively” to the horizon of its possibility in temporality and thereby shown to be but one, historically configured interpretation that itself emerges from, and is itself a response to, a destinal and historical happening of being itself, an antecedent configuring of possibility, or, in other words: the quiet force of the possible.
1 All translations, whether of works without an existing English translation or of works with an existing English translation, are the author’s own. Pagination will be given in the German edition, and where an English translation exists, in the English as well. The original German pagination of Being and Time, found also in the margins of both the Macquarrie and Robinson and the Stambaugh translations, will be used for citations throughout.
2 On the intrinsic belonging of possibility to the essence not merely of the animal, but of the living being in general, see in particular the 1929-30 course Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik: Welt—Endlichkeit—Einsamkeit. Gesamtausgabe Bd. 29/30. (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1983). Translated by William McNeill & Nicholas Walker as The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995). Here it is once again a question of the actuality of possibility—the latter conceived as being capable (Fähigsein)—where possibility is not to be conceived as mere logical possibility and the actuality of possibility is not to be reduced to the actual deployment or actualization of such capability:
In the last analysis, possibility and potentiality [Möglichsein und Können] belong precisely to the essence of the animal in its actuality in a quite specific sense—not merely in the sense that everything actual, inasmuch as it is at all, must already be possible as such. It is not this possibility, but rather being capable which belongs to the animal’s being actual, to the essence of life. Only something that is capable, and remains capable, is alive. (GA 29/30 343; Metaphysics 235)
Correlative to this sense of being capable as intrinsic to the essence of life in general is the possibility of death and of being dead:
Something which is no longer capable, irrespective of whether a capacity is used or not, is no longer alive. Something which does not exist in the manner of being capable cannot be dead either. The stone is never dead, because its being is not a being capable […] ‘Dead matter’ is a meaningless concept. Being capable is not the possibility of the organism as distinct from something actual, but is a constitutive moment of the way in which the animal as such is—of its being.” (GA 29/30 344; Metaphysics 236)
Once again, it is significant that Heidegger can here, at this level of the analysis, move back and forth, apparently seamlessly and unproblematically, between the animal and the essence of life in general; and where we can speak of the actuality of possibility as determinative of life in general, there we can also speak of death in general, of death as a possibility of life. Yet only apparently unproblematically: at another level of analysis, Heidegger will problematize precisely “whether death and death are the same in the case of man and animal,” thus whether life and life are the same, whether (the actuality of) possibility and possibility are the same (GA 29/30 388; Metaphysics 267). And Heidegger proceeds here to distinguish between “dying” (Sterben) as a possibility of the human being and “coming to an end” or “perishing” (Verenden) as the animal’s only possibility in relation to its death. At issue here, therefore, is ultimately the being of possibility, the way in which possibility “is” as a relation of being. Possibility, Heidegger will try to show (already in this 1929-30 course), can be given as possibility, as being possibility, only where there is logos, and only there can the possibility of impossibility be disclosed, thus, a relation to death as or in terms of possibility. The being of logos itself coincides with the thrown-projective character of Dasein, with its “irruption” into possibility, an irruption that ruptures possibility itself, quite literally takes it apart, dissects it, and only thereby is able to gather it as such. Here, we can only note in passing that this question of the being of possibility in relation to logos will be analyzed more incisively by Heidegger in the summer semester of 1931, in the course on the being and actuality of “force” or dunamis in relation to Aristotle’s analysis in Metaphysics Θ. See Aristotles, Metaphysik Θ 1-3: Von Wesen und Wirklichkeit der Kraft. Gesamtausgabe Bd. 33. (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1990). Translated as Aristotle’s Metaphysics Θ 1-3: On the Essence and Actuality of Force, by Walter Brogan & Peter Warnek (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995). We should note, furthermore, that Heidegger will maintain the distinction between “dying” (as a possibility of the human being) and “perishing” (as the possibility of the animal) throughout his later work, and ground this distinction in the phenomenon of the “as,” enabled by logos or the essence of language. For example, in the essay “Das Ding” (1950), where he writes: “[t]he mortals are the human beings. They are called mortals because they can die [sterben können]. To die means: to be capable of death as death [den Tod als Tod vermögen]. Only the human dies. The animal perishes.” In: Vorträge und Aufsätze (Pfullingen: Neske 1985), 171. Translated by Albert Hofstadter in Poetry, Language, Thought (New York: Harper & Row, 1971), 178. Or in the essay “Das Wesen der Sprache” (1957-58): “[m]ortals are those who can experience death as death. The animal is not capable of this. Yet the animal also cannot speak. The essential relationship between death and language flashes before us, but is as yet unthought.” In Unterwegs zur Sprache (Pfullingen: Neske, 1979), 215. Translated by Albert Hofstadter in On the Way to Language (New York: HarperCollins, 1982), 107. For an exploration of some of the stakes of this delimitation of the human from the animal see especially Jacques Derrida, De l’esprit (Paris: Galilée, 1987), and David Farrell Krell, Daimon Life: Heidegger and Life-Philosophy (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1992).
3 This opening up of the horizon of a world, correlative with the irruption into, and configuring of, possibility, is what Heidegger will thematize more explicitly in 1929 and 1930 as the antecedent event of world-formation (Weltbildung) that first enables any particular comportment of Dasein. See in particular the 1929 essay “Vom Wesen des Grundes” in Wegmarken. Gesamtausgabe Bd. 9 (Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1976), 123-75. Translated as “On the Essence of Ground” by William McNeill in Pathmarks (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 97-135; and the 1929-30 course The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude. (op. cit.).
4 The concept of facticity is said to entail “the being-in-the-world of a being ‘within the world,’ such that this being can understand itself as bound up [verhaftet] in its ‘destiny’ with the being of those beings that it encounters within its own world” Sein und Zeit. 17. Aufl. (Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1993), 56. Translated by John Macquarrie & Edward Robinson as Being and Time (Oxford: Blackwell, 1962). Also by Joan Stambaugh (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996). See also The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude. (op. cit) section 73, where letting oneself be bound (Sichbindenlassen) by beings is said to characterize the specific capability of the human, in contrast to the capacity of the animal.
5 One is here reminded of Hegel, who in the Preface to his Phenomenology writes of the “magical power” or “magical force” (Zauberkraft) that converts the negative into being and death into a non-actuality. The proximity of Heidegger to Hegel here is conspicuous. See Hegel, Phänomenologie des Geistes (Hamburg: Meiner, 1952), 29-30. Translated as Phenomenology of Spirit by A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), 19.
6 In referring to the “element” of the possible here, and to the essence of action as accomplishment (Vollbringen), I am alluding to the later discussion of possibility at the opening of the “Letter on ‘Humanism’.” (1946). See “Brief über den ‘Humanismus’.” in Wegmarken. (op. cit.). Translated as “Letter on ‘Humanism’” by Frank A. Capuzzi in Pathmarks (op. cit).
7 Thus Heidegger writes that, as thrown—precisely as thrown, thus as temporalized—“Dasein has been thrown into the mode of being of projection.” (SZ 145.) This is not Dasein’s choice. Paradoxical though it seems, we can catch and hold in presence what has been thrown only by releasing it, only by letting it go, and we can let it go, start it on its way, only by projecting it, by projecting it in terms of a possibility. Yet if it is not primarily or in the first instance Dasein that is projecting here, then what is it? What is it that first starts a possibility of being on its way? This primordial or originating force of thrownness, which Heidegger will name “the quiet force of the possible,” I shall suggest, is what is later thought by Heidegger as the “destining” or destinal happening of being (Geschick des Seins).
8 See also SZ 254.
9 See SZ 260.
10 The translation offered here differs from that of the existing English translations in rendering ausgehalten as “sustained.” An authentic relation or comportment toward this most extreme possibility of being does not merely “put up with” it (Macquarrie & Robinson) as something adversial; nor does such comportment merely “endure” it (Stambaugh). Rather, ausgehalten, the only past participle that Heidegger italicizes here, conveys the sense of a letting be of possibility as such, a sense that will be further explicated in the following paragraphs.
11 Again, I am suggesting a different translation of ermöglicht here than the Macquarrie & Robinson and Stambaugh translations, both of which have “makes possible.”
12 Entschlossen and Entschlossenheit, commonly rendered as “resolute” and “resoluteness” respectively, do not carry the sense of a willfulness closed off to other possibilities, as these English translations suggest, but rather—quite to the contrary, as Heidegger’s pairing of geschlossen (closed) and entschlossen here indicates—the sense of a radical openness toward the closure of the ekstatic future, thus, toward the “nothingness” that Dasein must factically ground as it affirms its own being in and through “action” (which, Heidegger insists, must be understood in a broad sense that encompasses all of Dasein’s comportments, including theoretical concerns: see SZ 300).
13 The German here reads: “Das faktische Dasein existiert gebürtig, und gebürtig stirbt es auch schon im Sinne des Seins zum Tode” (SZ 374). The existing English translations render existiert gebürtig by “exists as born,” implying that Dasein’s birth is an already accomplished fact or event, quite contrary to what Heidegger explicitly states here. It is significant that gebürtig conveys both the sense of “being born,” being “birthed” in the sense of coming into being, and of “giving birth,” in the sense of helping something come into being, and indeed is altogether undecidable with respect to these two inflections. The natality that Hannah Arendt would subsequently emphasize as belonging to the essence and possibility of action is here already seen as intrinsic to Dasein’s historicality.
14 See SZ 391, 397.
15 Significantly, Heidegger here embraces Nietzsche’s conception of critical history.
16 Again, it is significant in this regard that Heidegger chooses the German Kraft as the primary translation of Aristotle’s dunamis in his 1931 course On the Essence and Actuality of Force (op. cit.), but also employs the term Vermögen in the (more restricted) case of dunamis meta logou. The language of “possibility” (Möglichkeit) is conspicuously absent for the most part, although Können, “potentiality” (as in Dasein’s potentiality or potential for being) is also used at times. On the issue of terminology, cf. especially GA 33, 71-74. In his later, 1939 essay “On the Essence and Concept of Phusis in Aristotle’s Physics, B1,” Heidegger chooses not Kraft, but Eignung, “appropriateness,” to render its primary ontological sense: see especially “Vom Wesen und Begriff der physis. Aristoteles, Physik B,1” in Wegmarken. (op cit.), 286-87. Translated as “On the Essence and Concept of Phusis in Aristotle’s Physics, B1,” by Thomas Sheehan in Pathmarks (op. cit) 218-19.
17 In this reading, I am also arguing against Derrida’s suggestion, in his interview “‘Eating Well,’ or the Calculation of the Subject” with Jean-Luc Nancy, that thrownness, Geworfenheit—which Derrida rightly identifies as “a being-thrown that would be more primordial than subjectivity”—is “subsequently given to marginalization in Heidegger’s thinking.” See Who Comes After the Subject?, edited by Eduardo Cadava, Peter Connor, and Jean-Luc Nancy (New York: Routledge, 1991), 106-107.
Derrida, Jacques. De l’esprit. Paris: Galilée, 1987.
Derrida, Jacques. “Eating Well.” Who Comes After the Subject? Eds. Eduardo Cadava, Peter Connor, and Jean-Luc Nancy. New York: Routledge, 1991.
Derrida, Jacques. Of Spirit. Trans. Geoffrey Bennington and Rachel Bowlby. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989.
Hegel, G.W.F. Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. A. V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977.
Heidegger, Martin. Aristotle’s Metaphysics Θ 1-3: On the Essence and Actuality of Force. Trans. Walter Brogan and Peter Warnek. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995.
- - -. Aristotles, Metaphysik Θ 1-3: Von Wesen und Wirklichkeit der Kraft Gesamtausgabe Bd. 33. Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1990.
- - -. Being and Time. Trans. Joan Stambaugh. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996.
- - -. Being and Time. Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. Oxford: Blackwell, 1962.
- - -. “Brief über den ‘Humanismus.’” Wegmarken. Gesamtausgabe Bd. 9. Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1976.
- - -. “Das Ding.” Vorträge und Aufsätze. Pfullingen: Neske 1985.
- - -. “Das Wesen der Sprache.” Unterwegs zur Sprache. Pfullingen: Neske, 1979.
- - -. Die Grundbegriffe der Aristotelischen Philosophie. Gesamtausgabe Bd. 18. Frankfurt: Klostermann, 2002.
- - -. Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik: Welt—Endlichkeit—Einsamkeit. Gesamtausgabe Bd. 29/30. Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1983.
- - -. “Letter on ‘Humanism’” Trans. Frank A. Capuzzi. Pathmarks. Ed. William McNeill. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
- - -. Logik: Die Frage nach der Wahrheit. Gesamtausgabe Bd. 21. Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1976.
- - -. “On the Essence and Concept of Phusis in Aristotle’s Physics, B1.” Trans. Thomas Sheehan Pathmarks. Ed. William McNeill. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
- - -. “On the Essence of Ground.” Trans. William McNeill. Pathmarks. Ed. William McNeill. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
- - -. Sein und Zeit. 17. Aufl. Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1993.
- - -. The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World, Finitude, Solitude Trans.William McNeill and Nicholas Walker. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995.
- - -. “The Thing.” Poetry, Language, Thought. New York: Harper & Row, 1971.
- - -. “The Way to Language.” On the Way to Language. New York: HarperCollins, 1982.
- - -. “Vom Wesen des Grundes.” Wegmarken. Gesamtausgabe Bd. 9. Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1976.
- - -. “Vom Wesen und Begriff der physis. Aristoteles, Physik B,1.” Wegmarken. Gesamtausgabe Bd. 9. Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1976.
Krell, David Farrell. Daimon Life: Heidegger and Life-Philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1992.
William McNeill - Rethinking the Possible: On the Radicalization of Possibility in Heidegger’s Being and Time
Original PDF version.